On the legitimacy of the meta-philosophical interrogation in philosophy of biology

Authors

  • E. Joaquín Suárez-Ruíz Universidad Nacional de La Plata

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.22370/rhv2019iss14pp377-393

Keywords:

philosophy of biology, philosophical naturalism, meta-philosophy, anthropocentrism

Abstract

One of the most controversial and currently developed lines of research in philosophy of biology is that in which philosophers investigate pre-Darwinian assumptions that would still be present at the base of other philosophical sub-disciplines, such as ethics, epistemology, philosophy of language, etc. This type of inquiry, which I will call here “meta-philosophical interrogation,” can be thought as a complementary approach to the epistemological one, which allows us to broaden the critical approach of the discipline in question. The objective of this article will be to analyze the characteristics of the “meta-philosophical interrogation” and to argue about its legitimacy as a way of inquiry proper to the philosophy of biology.

References

Andler, D. (2016). La silhouette de l’humain. Quelle place pour le naturalisme dans le monde d’aujourd’hui? Paris: Gallimard.

Baumard, N. (2016). The origins of fairness, how evolution explains our moral nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Blackburn, S. (2005). The oxford dictionary of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Boddice, R. (ed.) (2011). Humans, animals, environments. Leiden: Brill.

Brand, C. (ed.) (2016). Dual-process theories in moral psychology. Wiesbaden: Springer.

Butcharov, P. (2015). Anthropocentrism in philosophy. Berlin: De Gruyter.

Caponi, G. (2018). ¿Qué quiere decir “naturalizar”? Ludus Vitalis, XXVI(50): 185-188.

Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Putnam.

Dennett, D. (2004). La evolución de la libertad. Barcelona: Paidos.

Dewey, J. (1911). The influence of Darwin on Philosophy. The Philosophical Review, 20(2): 219-221.

Diéguez, A. (2014a). Delimitación y defensa del naturalismo metodológico (en la ciencia y en la filosofía). En R. Gutierrez-Lombardo, J. Sanmartín (eds.), La filosofía desde la ciencia, pp.21-49. México DF: Centro de Estudios Filosóficos, Políticos y Sociales Vicente Lombardo Toledano.

Diéguez, A. (2014b). Pensamiento conceptual en animales. En A. Diéguez, J. M. Atencia, Naturaleza animal y humana, pp. 83-114. Madrid: Biblioteca nueva.

Diéguez, A., Atencia, J. M. (2014). Naturaleza animal y humana. Madrid: Biblioteca nueva.

Gould, J. L. (2002). Learning instincts. En J. Wixted, H. Pashler (eds.), Steven’s handbook of experimental psychology: Learning, motivation, and emotion, pp. 239-257. New Jersey: John Wiley & Sons. doi: https://doi.org/10.1002/0471214426.pas0306

Greene, J. (2013). Moral tribes. Nueva York: The Penguin Press.

Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108: 814-834.

Ingmanson, E. (1996). Tool-using behavior in Wild Pan Paniscus: Social and Ecological Considerations. En A. Russon et al. (eds.), Reaching into Thought: The Minds of the Great Apes, pp. 190-210. Nueva York : Cambridge University Press.

Kitcher, P. (2011). The ethical Project. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Lepore, E., Ludwig, K. (eds.) (2013). A companion to Donald Davidson. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

McGrew, W. (1998). Culture in nonhuman primates? Annual Review of Anthropology, 27: 301-28.

Popp, J. (2007). Evolution’s first philosopher, John Dewey and the continuity of nature. Nueva York: State University of New York Press.

Ruse, M. (2005). Altruismo: una perspectiva naturalista darwiniana. Saga, 10: 95-110. Traducción: Maximiliano Martínez y Fernando Melo. El texto original puede hallarse en S. Post, et al. (eds.) (2002), Altruism and altruistic love. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Schaeffer, J. M. (2009). El fin de la excepción humana. Barcelona: Marbot.

Sapolsky, R. (2017). Behave: the biology of humans at our best and worst. Nueva York: Penguin.

Sapolsky, R., Share, L. (2004). A pacific culture among wild baboons, its emergence and transmission. Public Library of Science Biology, 2: e106-13.

Singer, P. (2009). Liberación Animal. Madrid: Trotta.

Sterelny, K. (2006). Folk logic and animal rationality. En S. Hurley, M. Nudds (eds.), Rational Animals? pp. 293-311. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Suárez-Ruíz, E. J. (2017). Filosofía post-darwiniana: sobre la relevancia de la continuidad evolutiva en la comprensión de la moral. Tesis de licenciatura, Dpto. de Filosofía, FaHCE, UNLP.

Suárez-Ruíz, E. J. (2018). Para una caracterización filosófica de la continuidad evolutiva. Revista Latinoamericana de Estudios Críticos Animales, 2: 139-158.

Suárez-Ruíz, E. J. (2019). El otro lado de la filosofía de la biología: una problematización de lo epistemológico como límite disciplinar. Nuevo Itinerario, 15: 58-74.

Toda, K., Platt, M. L. (2015). Animal cognition: monkeys pass the mirror test. Current biology, 25(12): 64-66.

Tomasello, M. (2000). Primate cognition: introduction to the issue. Cognitive science, 24(3): 351-361.

Toribio, J. (2010). The animal concepts debate: a metaphilosophical take. Teorema, XXIX(2): 11-24.

Tonutti, S. (2011). Anthropocentrism and the Definition of ‘Culture’ as a Marker of the Human/Animal Divide. R. Boddice (ed.), Humans, Animals, Environments, pp.183-199. Leiden: Brill.

Volokh, E. (2003). The mechanisms of the slipperly slope. Harvard Law Review, 116(4): 1026-1137.

Waal, F. de (1991). The chimpanzee’s sense of social regularity and its relation to the human sense of justice. American Behavioral Scientist, 34: 335-349.

Waal, F. de (2007). Primates y filósofos. Barcelona: Paidos.

Published

2019-12-29

How to Cite

Suárez-Ruíz, E. J. (2019). On the legitimacy of the meta-philosophical interrogation in philosophy of biology. Revista De Humanidades De Valparaíso, (14), 377–393. https://doi.org/10.22370/rhv2019iss14pp377-393

Similar Articles

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 > >> 

You may also start an advanced similarity search for this article.