The synthetic thesis of truth helps mitigate the reproducibility crisis and is an inspiration for predictive ecology

Authors

  • Luis Marone ECODES, Instituto Argentino de Investigaciones de las Zonas Áridas, CONICET / Facultad de Ciencias Exactas y Naturales, Universidad Nacional de Cuyo http://orcid.org/0000-0002-6773-643X
  • Javier Lopez de Casenave ECODES, Departamento de Ecología, Genética y Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias Exactas y Naturales, Universidad de Buenos Aires / IEGEBA (UBA–CONICET)
  • Rafael González del Solar ECODES

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.22370/rhv2019iss14pp363-376

Keywords:

philosophy of science, scientific realism, truth thesis, empirical and rational support, causal mechanisms

Abstract

There are currently serious concerns that published scientific findings often fail to be reproducible, and that some solutions may be gleaned by attending the several methodological and sociological recommendations that could be found in the literature. However, researchers would also arrive at some answers by considering the advice of the philosophy of science, particularly semantics, about theses on truth related to scientific realism. Sometimes scientists understand the correspondence thesis of truth (CTT) as asserting that the next unique empirical confirmation of a hypothesis suffices to attribute truth to it provisionally. Such empiricist bias is not necessarily at the core of CTT, but Mario Bunge proposed the synthetic thesis of truth (STT), based on CTT, to explicitly avoid the bias. STT requires considering a hypothesis corroborated, both by purely empirical confirmation and external consistency or compatibility with the bulk of existing background knowledge (systemicity). While a capricious understanding of CTT could be rigged to recommend the “one shot game” in hypothesis testing, STT clearly demands the use of multiple approaches, empirical as well as theoretical, and it asserts that a scientific test is effective to the extent to which it is neither purely empirical, nor viewed in isolation. Pattern consistency (empirical control) together with an understanding of causal relations (rational together with empirical control) make confirmed hypotheses robust and more reliable. The militancy of the double mechanism of hypothesis control of STT can help mitigate the reproducibility crisis. Earl Werner’s research program in community ecology is an example of the (implicit) use of STT criteria, which leads to the development of reliable, cross-checked, ecological results, with high predictive capacity.

Author Biography

Luis Marone, ECODES, Instituto Argentino de Investigaciones de las Zonas Áridas, CONICET / Facultad de Ciencias Exactas y Naturales, Universidad Nacional de Cuyo

Investigador CONICET y Profesor Titular UN Cuyo, Mendoza, Argentina

References

Baker, M. (2016). Is there a reproducibility crisis? Nature, 533: 452-454. doi: https://doi.org/10.1038/533452a

Berg, J. (2018). Progress on reproducibility. Science, 359: 9. doi: https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aar8654

Bunge, M. (1997). Mechanism and explanation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 27: 410-465. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/004839319702700402

Bunge, M. (1998). Philosophy of Science. Volume 2, From Explanation to Justification. New York: Routledge. doi: https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315126388

Bunge, M. (1999). Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: Prometheus Books.

Bunge, M. (2006). Chasing reality: Strife over Realism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. doi: https://doi.org/10.3138/9781442672857

Bunge, M. (2012). The correspondence theory of truth. Semiotica, 188: 65-75. doi: https://doi.org/10.1515/sem-2012-0004

Bunge, M. (2017). Evaluating scientific research projects: The units of science in the making. Foundations of Science, 22: 455-469. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-015-9474-3

Cohen, B. A. (2017). How should novelty be valued in science? eLife, 6 (art. e28699). doi: https://doi.org/10.7554/elife.28699

Editors (2014). Journals unite for reproducibility. Nature, 515: 7. doi: https://doi.org/10.1038/515007a

Editors (2016). Reality check on reproducibility. Nature, 533: 437. doi: https://doi.org/10.1038/533437a

Hairston, N. G. (1989). Ecological experiments: Purpose, design, and execution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/cbo9780511608513

Higginson, A. D., Munafó, M. R. (2016). Current incentives for scientists lead to underpowered studies with erroneous conclusions. PLoS Biology, 14 (art. e2000995). doi: https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.2000995

Ioannidis, J. P. A., Ntzani, E. E., Trikalinos, T. A., Contopoulos-Ioannidis, D. G. (2001). Replication validity of genetic association studies. Nature Genetics, 29: 306-309. doi: https://doi.org/10.1038/ng749

Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2005a). Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Medicine, 2 (art. e124). doi: https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124

Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2005b). Contradicted and initially stronger effects in highly cited clinical research. JAMA, 294: 218-228. doi: https://doi.org/10.1001/jama.294.2.218

Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2014). How to make more published research true. PLoS Medicine, 11 (art. 1001747). doi: https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1001747

Ives, A. R. (2018). Informative irreproducibility and the use of experiments in ecology. BioScience, 68: 746-747. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/biosci/biy090

Johnson, D. H. (2002). The importance of replication in wildlife research. Journal of Wildlife Management, 66: 919-932. doi: https://doi.org/10.2307/3802926

Lehrer, J. (2010). The truth wears off. Is there something wrong with the scientific method? The New Yorker, December, 13: 52-57.

Lombardi, O. (2016). Carta abierta: acerca del mundo, los mundos y el papel de la filosofía. Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso, 8: 129-145. doi: https://doi.org/10.22370/rhv.2016.8.501

Mahner, M. (2001). Scientific Realism. New York: Prometheus Books.

Marone, L., Bunge, M. (1998). La explicación en ecología. Boletín de la Asociación Argentina de Ecología, 7: 35-37.

Marone, L., Galetto, L. (2011). El doble papel de las hipótesis en la investigación ecológica y su relación con el método hipotético deductivo. Ecología Austral, 21: 201-216.

Marone, L., Lopez de Casenave, J., Cueto, V. R. (2000). Granivory in southern South American deserts: Conceptual issues and current evidence. BioScience, 50: 123-132. doi: https://doi.org/10.1641/0006-3568(2000)050[0123:gissad]2.3.co;2

Marone, L., Lopez de Casenave, J., Milesi, F. A., Cueto, V. R. (2008). Can seed-eating birds exert top-down effects on grasses of the Monte desert? Oikos, 117: 611-619. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0030-1299.2008.16506.x

Marone, L., Olmedo, M., Valdés, D. Y., Zarco, A., Lopez de Casenave, J., Pol, R. G. (2017). Diet switching of seed-eating birds wintering in grazed habitats of the central Monte desert, Argentina. Condor: Ornithological Applications, 119: 673-682. doi: https://doi.org/10.1650/condor-17-61.1

McNutt, M. (2014). Reproducibility. Science, 343: 229. doi: https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aaa1724

Munafó, M. R., Smith, G. D. (2018). Repeating experiments is not enough. Nature, 553: 399-401. doi: https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-018-01023-3

Pol, R. G., Sagario, M. C., Marone, L. (2014). Grazing impact on desert plants and soil seed banks: implications for seed-eating animals. Acta Oecologica, 55: 58-65. doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.actao.2013.11.009

Polis, G. A., Wise, D. H., Hurd, S. D., Sánchez-Piñero, F., Wagner, J. D., Jackson, C. T., Barnes, J. D. (1998). The interplay between natural history and field experimentation. In W. j. Resetarits, J. Bernardo (eds.), Experimental ecology. Issues and perspectives, pp. 254-280. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: https://doi.org/10.2307/1447995

Ríos, J. M., Mangione, A. M., Marone, L. (2012). Effects of nutritional and anti-nutritional properties of seeds on the feeding ecology of seed-eating birds of the Monte Desert, Argentina. Condor, 114: 44-55. doi: https://doi.org/10.1525/cond.2012.110043

Russell, B. (1918/1998). Philosophy of Logical Atomism. Chicago: Open Court.

Sagario, M. C., Cueto, V. R., Zarco, A., Pol, R., Marone, L. (2020) Predicting how seed-eating passerines respond to cattle grazing in a semi-arid grassland using seed preferences and diet. Agriculture, Ecosystems and Environment, 289 (art. 106736). doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.agee.2019.106736

Smith, E. F. (1920). An introduction to bacterial diseases of plants. Philadelphia: WB Saunders Company. doi: https://doi.org/10.5962/bhl.title.13485

Stegenga, J. (2009). Robustness, discordance, and relevance. Philosophy of Science, 76: 650-661. doi: https://doi.org/10.1086/605819

Tarski, A. (1983). Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

Werner, E. E. (1998). Ecological experiments and a research program in community ecology. In W. J., Resetarits, J. Bernardo (eds.), Experimental ecology. Issues and perspectives, pp. 3-26. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: https://doi.org/10.2307/1447995

Young, N. S., Ioannidis, J. P. A., Al-Ubaydli, O. (2008). Why current publication practices may distort science. PLoS Medicine, 5 (art. e210). doi: https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.0050201

Downloads

Published

2019-12-29

How to Cite

Marone, L., Lopez de Casenave, J., & González del Solar, R. (2019). The synthetic thesis of truth helps mitigate the reproducibility crisis and is an inspiration for predictive ecology. Revista De Humanidades De Valparaíso, (14), 363–376. https://doi.org/10.22370/rhv2019iss14pp363-376

Similar Articles

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 > >> 

You may also start an advanced similarity search for this article.